Web
and Book design, |
Click
Here to return to |
CHAPTER X. ON THE GEOLOGICAL SUCCESSION OF ORGANIC BEINGS. On the slow and successive appearance of new species—On their different rates of change—Species once lost do not reappear—Groups of species follow the same general rules in their appearance and disappearance as do single species—On Extinction—On simultaneous changes in the forms of life throughout the world—On the affinities of extinct species to each other and to living species—On the state of development of ancient forms—On the succession of the same types within the same areas—Summary of preceding and present chapters. LET us now
see whether the several facts and rules relating to the geological succession
of organic beings, better accord with the common view of the immutability of
species, or with that of their slow and gradual modification, through descent
and natural selection. New
species have appeared very slowly, one after another, both on the land and in
the waters. Lyell has shown that it is hardly possible to resist the evidence
on this head in the case of the several tertiary stages; and every year tends
to fill up the blanks between them, and to make the percentage system of lost
and new forms more gradual. In some of the most recent beds, though undoubtedly
of high antiquity if measured by years, only one or two species are lost forms,
and only one or two are new forms, having here appeared for the first time,
either locally, or, as far as we know, on the face of the earth. If we may
trust the observations of Philippi in Sicily, the successive changes in the
marine inhabitants of that island have been many and most gradual. The
secondary formations are more broken; but, as Bronn has remarked, neither the
appearance nor disappearance of their many now extinct species has been
simultaneous in each separate formation. Species of
different genera and classes have not changed at the same rate, or in the same
degree. In the oldest tertiary beds a few living shells may still be found in
the midst of a multitude of extinct forms. Falconer has given a striking
instance of a similar fact, in an existing crocodile associated with many
strange and lost mammals and reptiles in the sub-Himalayan deposits. The
Silurian Lingula differs but little from the living species of this genus;
whereas most of the other Silurian Molluscs and all the Crustaceans have
changed greatly. The productions of the land seem to change at a quicker rate
than those of the sea, of which a striking instance has lately been observed in
Switzerland. There is some reason to believe that organisms, considered high in
the scale of nature, change more quickly than those that are low: though there
are exceptions to this rule. The amount of organic change, as Pictet has
remarked, does not strictly correspond with the succession of our geological
formations; so that between each two consecutive formations, the forms of life
have seldom changed in exactly the same degree. Yet if we compare any but the
most closely related formations, all the species will be found to have
undergone some change. When a species has once disappeared from the face of the
earth, we have reason to believe that the same identical form never reappears.
The strongest apparent exception to this latter rule, is that of the so-called
“colonies” of M. Barrande, which intrude for a period in the midst of an older
formation, and then allow the pre-existing fauna to reappear; but Lyell’s
explanation, namely, that it is a case of temporary migration from a distinct
geographical province, seems to me satisfactory. These
several facts accord well with my theory. I believe in no fixed law of
development, causing all the inhabitants of a country to change abruptly, or
simultaneously, or to an equal degree. The process of modification must be
extremely slow. The variability of each species is quite independent of that of
all others. Whether such variability be taken advantage of by natural
selection, and whether the variations be accumulated to a greater or lesser
amount, thus causing a greater or lesser amount of modification in the varying
species, depends on many complex contingencies,—on the variability being of a
beneficial nature, on the power of intercrossing, on the rate of breeding, on
the slowly changing physical conditions of the country, and more especially on
the nature of the other inhabitants with which the varying species comes into
competition. Hence it is by no means surprising that one species should retain
the same identical form much longer than others; or, if changing, that it
should change less. We see the same fact in geographical distribution; for
instance, in the land-shells and coleopterous insects of Madeira having come to
differ considerably from their nearest allies on the continent of Europe,
whereas the marine shells and birds have remained unaltered. We can perhaps
understand the apparently quicker rate of change in terrestrial and in more
highly organised productions compared with marine and lower productions, by the
more complex relations of the higher beings to their organic and inorganic
conditions of life, as explained in a former chapter. When many of the
inhabitants of a country have become modified and improved, we can understand,
on the principle of competition, and on that of the many all-important
relations of organism to organism, that any form which does not become in some
degree modified and improved, will be liable to be exterminated. Hence we can
see why all the species in the same region do at last, if we look to wide
enough intervals of time, become modified; for those which do not change will
become extinct. In members
of the same class the average amount of change, during long and equal periods
of time, may, perhaps, be nearly the same; but as the accumulation of
long-enduring fossiliferous formations depends on great masses of sediment
having been deposited on areas whilst subsiding, our formations have been
almost necessarily accumulated at wide and irregularly intermittent intervals;
consequently the amount of organic change exhibited by the fossils embedded in
consecutive formations is not equal. Each formation, on this view, does not
mark a new and complete act of creation, but only an occasional scene, taken
almost at hazard, in a slowly changing drama. We can
clearly understand why a species when once lost should never reappear, even if
the very same conditions of life, organic and inorganic, should recur. For
though the offspring of one species might be adapted (and no doubt this has
occurred in innumerable instances) to fill the exact place of another species
in the economy of nature, and thus supplant it; yet the two forms—the old and
the new—would not be identically the same; for both would almost certainly
inherit different characters from their distinct progenitors. For instance, it
is just possible, if our fantail-pigeons were all destroyed, that fanciers, by
striving during long ages for the same object, might make a new breed hardly
distinguishable from our present fantail; but if the parent rock-pigeon were
also destroyed, and in nature we have every reason to believe that the
parent-form will generally be supplanted and exterminated by its improved
offspring, it is quite incredible that a fantail, identical with the existing
breed, could be raised from any other species of pigeon, or even from the other
well-established races of the domestic pigeon, for the newly-formed fantail
would be almost sure to inherit from its new progenitor some slight
characteristic differences. Groups of
species, that is, genera and families, follow the same general rules in their
appearance and disappearance as do single species, changing more or less
quickly, and in a greater or lesser degree. A group does not reappear after it
has once disappeared; or its existence, as long as it lasts, is continuous. I
am aware that there are some apparent exceptions to this rule, but the
exceptions are surprisingly few, so few, that E. Forbes, Pictet, and Woodward
(though all strongly opposed to such views as I maintain) admit its truth; and
the rule strictly accords with my theory. For as all the species of the same
group have descended from some one species, it is clear that as long as any
species of the group have appeared in the long succession of ages, so long must
its members have continuously existed, in order to have generated either new
and modified or the same old and unmodified forms. Species of the genus
Lingula, for instance, must have continuously existed by an unbroken succession
of generations, from the lowest Silurian stratum to the present day. We have
seen in the last chapter that the species of a group sometimes falsely appear
to have come in abruptly; and I have attempted to give an explanation of this
fact, which if true would have been fatal to my views. But such cases are
certainly exceptional; the general rule being a gradual increase in number,
till the group reaches its maximum, and then, sooner or later, it gradually
decreases. If the number of the species of a genus, or the number of the genera
of a family, be represented by a vertical line of varying thickness, crossing
the successive geological formations in which the species are found, the line
will sometimes falsely appear to begin at its lower end, not in a sharp point,
but abruptly; it then gradually thickens upwards, sometimes keeping for a space
of equal thickness, and ultimately thins out in the upper beds, marking the
decrease and final extinction of the species. This gradual increase in number
of the species of a group is strictly conformable with my theory; as the
species of the same genus, and the genera of the same family, can increase only
slowly and progressively; for the process of modification and the production of
a number of allied forms must be slow and gradual,—one species giving rise
first to two or three varieties, these being slowly converted into species,
which in their turn produce by equally slow steps other species, and so on,
like the branching of a great tree from a single stem, till the group becomes
large. On
Extinction.—We have as yet spoken only incidentally of the
disappearance of species and of groups of species. On the theory of natural
selection the extinction of old forms and the production of new and improved
forms are intimately connected together. The old notion of all the inhabitants
of the earth having been swept away at successive periods by catastrophes, is
very generally given up, even by those geologists, as Elie de Beaumont,
Murchison, Barrande, &c., whose general views would naturally lead them to
this conclusion. On the contrary, we have every reason to believe, from the
study of the tertiary formations, that species and groups of species gradually
disappear, one after another, first from one spot, then from another, and
finally from the world. Both single species and whole groups of species last
for very unequal periods; some groups, as we have seen, having endured from the
earliest known dawn of life to the present day; some having disappeared before
the close of the palæozoic period. No fixed law seems to determine the length
of time during which any single species or any single genus endures. There is
reason to believe that the complete extinction of the species of a group is
generally a slower process than their production: if the appearance and
disappearance of a group of species be represented, as before, by a vertical
line of varying thickness, the line is found to taper more gradually at its
upper end, which marks the progress of extermination, than at its lower end,
which marks the first appearance and increase in numbers of the species. In
some cases, however, the extermination of whole groups of beings, as of
ammonites towards the close of the secondary period, has been wonderfully
sudden. The whole
subject of the extinction of species has been involved in the most gratuitous
mystery. Some authors have even supposed that as the individual has a definite
length of life, so have species a definite duration. No one I think can have
marvelled more at the extinction of species, than I have done. When I found in
La Plata the tooth of a horse embedded with the remains of Mastodon,
Megatherium, Toxodon, and other extinct monsters, which all co-existed with
still living shells at a very late geological period, I was filled with
astonishment; for seeing that the horse, since its introduction by the
Spaniards into South America, has run wild over the whole country and has
increased in numbers at an unparalleled rate, I asked myself what could so
recently have exterminated the former horse under conditions of life apparently
so favourable. But how utterly groundless was my astonishment! Professor Owen
soon perceived that the tooth, though so like that of the existing horse,
belonged to an extinct species. Had this horse been still living, but in some
degree rare, no naturalist would have felt the least surprise at its rarity;
for rarity is the attribute of a vast number of species of all classes, in all
countries. If we ask ourselves why this or that species is rare, we answer that
something is unfavourable in its conditions of life; but what that something
is, we can hardly ever tell. On the supposition of the fossil horse still
existing as a rare species, we might have felt certain from the analogy of all
other mammals, even of the slow-breeding elephant, and from the history of the
naturalisation of the domestic horse in South America, that under more
favourable conditions it would in a very few years have stocked the whole
continent. But we could not have told what the unfavourable conditions were
which checked its increase, whether some one or several contingencies, and at
what period of the horse’s life, and in what degree, they severally acted. If
the conditions had gone on, however slowly, becoming less and less favourable,
we assuredly should not have perceived the fact, yet the fossil horse would
certainly have become rarer and rarer, and finally extinct;—its place being
seized on by some more successful competitor. It is most
difficult always to remember that the increase of every living being is
constantly being checked by unperceived injurious agencies; and that these same
unperceived agencies are amply sufficient to cause rarity, and finally
extinction. We see in many cases in the more recent tertiary formations, that
rarity precedes extinction; and we know that this has been the progress of
events with those animals which have been exterminated, either locally or
wholly, through man’s agency. I may repeat what I published in 1845, namely,
that to admit that species generally become rare before they become extinct—to
feel no surprise at the rarity of a species, and yet to marvel greatly when it
ceases to exist, is much the same as to admit that sickness in the individual
is the forerunner of death—to feel no surprise at sickness, but when the sick
man dies, to wonder and to suspect that he died by some unknown deed of
violence. The theory
of natural selection is grounded on the belief that each new variety, and
ultimately each new species, is produced and maintained by having some
advantage over those with which it comes into competition; and the consequent
extinction of less-favoured forms almost inevitably follows. It is the same
with our domestic productions: when a new and slightly improved variety has
been raised, it at first supplants the less improved varieties in the same
neighbourhood; when much improved it is transported far and near, like our
short-horn cattle, and takes the place of other breeds in other countries. Thus
the appearance of new forms and the disappearance of old forms, both natural
and artificial, are bound together. In certain flourishing groups, the number
of new specific forms which have been produced within a given time is probably
greater than that of the old forms which have been exterminated; but we know
that the number of species has not gone on indefinitely increasing, at least
during the later geological periods, so that looking to later times we may
believe that the production of new forms has caused the extinction of about the
same number of old forms. The
competition will generally be most severe, as formerly explained and
illustrated by examples, between the forms which are most like each other in
all respects. Hence the
improved and modified descendants of a species will generally cause the
extermination of the parent-species; and if many new forms have been developed
from any one species, the nearest allies of that species, i.e. the
species of the same genus, will be the most liable to extermination. Thus, as I
believe, a number of new species descended from one species, that is a new
genus, comes to supplant an old genus, belonging to the same family. But it
must often have happened that a new species belonging to some one group will
have seized on the place occupied by a species belonging to a distinct group,
and thus caused its extermination; and if many allied forms be developed from
the successful intruder, many will have to yield their places; and it will
generally be allied forms, which will suffer from some inherited inferiority in
common. But whether it be species belonging to the same or to a distinct class,
which yield their places to other species which have been modified and
improved, a few of the sufferers may often long be preserved, from being fitted
to some peculiar line of life, or from inhabiting some distant and isolated
station, where they have escaped severe competition. For instance, a single
species of Trigonia, a great genus of shells in the secondary formations,
survives in the Australian seas; and a few members of the great and almost
extinct group of Ganoid fishes still inhabit our fresh waters. Therefore the
utter extinction of a group is generally, as we have seen, a slower process
than its production. With
respect to the apparently sudden extermination of whole families or orders, as
of Trilobites at the close of the palæozoic period and of Ammonites at the
close of the secondary period, we must remember what has been already said on
the probable wide intervals of time between our consecutive formations; and in
these intervals there may have been much slow extermination. Moreover, when by
sudden immigration or by unusually rapid development, many species of a new
group have taken possession of a new area, they will have exterminated in a
correspondingly rapid manner many of the old inhabitants; and the forms which
thus yield their places will commonly be allied, for they will partake of some
inferiority in common. Thus, as
it seems to me, the manner in which single species and whole groups of species
become extinct, accords well with the theory of natural selection. We need not
marvel at extinction; if we must marvel, let it be at our presumption in
imagining for a moment that we understand the many complex contingencies, on
which the existence of each species depends. If we forget for an instant, that
each species tends to increase inordinately, and that some check is always in
action, yet seldom perceived by us, the whole economy of nature will be utterly
obscured. Whenever we can precisely say why this species is more abundant in
individuals than that; why this species and not another can be naturalised in a
given country; then, and not till then, we may justly feel surprise why we
cannot account for the extinction of this particular species or group of
species. On the
Forms of Life changing almost simultaneously throughout the World.—Scarcely
any palæontological discovery is more striking than the fact, that the forms of
life change almost simultaneously throughout the world. Thus our European Chalk
formation can be recognised in many distant parts of the world, under the most
different climates, where not a fragment of the mineral chalk itself can be
found; namely, in North America, in equatorial South America, in Tierra del
Fuego, at the Cape of Good Hope, and in the peninsula of India. For at these
distant points, the organic remains in certain beds present an unmistakeable
degree of resemblance to those of the Chalk. It is not that the same species
are met with; for in some cases not one species is identically the same, but
they belong to the same families, genera, and sections of genera, and sometimes
are similarly characterised in such trifling points as mere superficial
sculpture. Moreover other forms, which are not found in the Chalk of Europe,
but which occur in the formations either above or below, are similarly absent
at these distant points of the world. In the several successive palæozoic
formations of Russia, Western Europe and North America, a similar parallelism
in the forms of life has been observed by several authors: so it is, according
to Lyell, with the several European and North American tertiary deposits. Even
if the few fossil species which are common to the Old and New Worlds be kept
wholly out of view, the general parallelism in the successive forms of life, in
the stages of the widely separated palæozoic and tertiary periods, would still
be manifest, and the several formations could be easily correlated. These
observations, however, relate to the marine inhabitants of distant parts of the
world: we have not sufficient data to judge whether the productions of the land
and of fresh water change at distant points in the same parallel manner. We may
doubt whether they have thus changed: if the Megatherium, Mylodon,
Macrauchenia, and Toxodon had been brought to Europe from La Plata, without any
information in regard to their geological position, no one would have suspected
that they had coexisted with still living sea-shells; but as these anomalous
monsters coexisted with the Mastodon and Horse, it might at least have been
inferred that they had lived during one of the latter tertiary stages. When the
marine forms of life are spoken of as having changed simultaneously throughout
the world, it must not be supposed that this expression relates to the same
thousandth or hundred-thousandth year, or even that it has a very strict
geological sense; for if all the marine animals which live at the present day
in Europe, and all those that lived in Europe during the pleistocene period (an
enormously remote period as measured by years, including the whole glacial
epoch), were to be compared with those now living in South America or in
Australia, the most skilful naturalist would hardly be able to say whether the
existing or the pleistocene inhabitants of Europe resembled most closely those
of the southern hemisphere. So, again, several highly competent observers
believe that the existing productions of the United States are more closely
related to those which lived in Europe during certain later tertiary stages,
than to those which now live here; and if this be so, it is evident that fossiliferous
beds deposited at the present day on the shores of North America would
hereafter be liable to be classed with somewhat older European beds.
Nevertheless, looking to a remotely future epoch, there can, I think, be little
doubt that all the more modern marine formations, namely, the upper
pliocene, the pleistocene and strictly modern beds, of Europe, North and South
America, and Australia, from containing fossil remains in some degree allied,
and from not including those forms which are only found in the older underlying
deposits, would be correctly ranked as simultaneous in a geological sense. The fact
of the forms of life changing simultaneously, in the above large sense, at
distant parts of the world, has greatly struck those admirable observers, MM.
de Verneuil and d’Archiac. After referring to the parallelism of the palæozoic
forms of life in various parts of Europe, they add, “If struck by this strange
sequence, we turn our attention to North America, and there discover a series
of analogous phenomena, it will appear certain that all these modifications of
species, their extinction, and the introduction of new ones, cannot be owing to
mere changes in marine currents or other causes more or less local and
temporary, but depend on general laws which govern the whole animal kingdom.”
M. Barrande has made forcible remarks to precisely the same effect. It is,
indeed, quite futile to look to changes of currents, climate, or other physical
conditions, as the cause of these great mutations in the forms of life
throughout the world, under the most different climates. We must, as Barrande
has remarked, look to some special law. We shall see this more clearly when we
treat of the present distribution of organic beings, and find how slight is the
relation between the physical conditions of various countries, and the nature
of their inhabitants. This great
fact of the parallel succession of the forms of life throughout the world, is
explicable on the theory of natural selection. New species are formed by new
varieties arising, which have some advantage over older forms; and those forms,
which are already dominant, or have some advantage over the other forms in
their own country, would naturally oftenest give rise to new varieties or
incipient species; for these latter must be victorious in a still higher degree
in order to be preserved and to survive. We have distinct evidence on this
head, in the plants which are dominant, that is, which are commonest in their
own homes, and are most widely diffused, having produced the greatest number of
new varieties. It is also natural that the dominant, varying, and far-spreading
species, which already have invaded to a certain extent the territories of
other species, should be those which would have the best chance of spreading
still further, and of giving rise in new countries to new varieties and
species. The process of diffusion may often be very slow, being dependent on
climatal and geographical changes, or on strange accidents, but in the long run
the dominant forms will generally succeed in spreading. The diffusion would, it
is probable, be slower with the terrestrial inhabitants of distinct continents
than with the marine inhabitants of the continuous sea. We might therefore
expect to find, as we apparently do find, a less strict degree of parallel
succession in the productions of the land than of the sea. Dominant
species spreading from any region might encounter still more dominant species,
and then their triumphant course, or even their existence, would cease. We know
not at all precisely what are all the conditions most favourable for the
multiplication of new and dominant species; but we can, I think, clearly see
that a number of individuals, from giving a better chance of the appearance of
favourable variations, and that severe competition with many already existing
forms, would be highly favourable, as would be the power of spreading into new
territories. A certain amount of isolation, recurring at long intervals of
time, would probably be also favourable, as before explained. One quarter of
the world may have been most favourable for the production of new and dominant
species on the land, and another for those in the waters of the sea. If two
great regions had been for a long period favourably circumstanced in an equal
degree, whenever their inhabitants met, the battle would be prolonged and
severe; and some from one birthplace and some from the other might be
victorious. But in the course of time, the forms dominant in the highest
degree, wherever produced, would tend everywhere to prevail. As they prevailed,
they would cause the extinction of other and inferior forms; and as these
inferior forms would be allied in groups by inheritance, whole groups would
tend slowly to disappear; though here and there a single member might long be
enabled to survive. Thus, as
it seems to me, the parallel, and, taken in a large sense, simultaneous,
succession of the same forms of life throughout the world, accords well with
the principle of new species having been formed by dominant species spreading
widely and varying; the new species thus produced being themselves dominant
owing to inheritance, and to having already had some advantage over their
parents or over other species; these again spreading, varying, and producing
new species. The forms which are beaten and which yield their places to the new
and victorious forms, will generally be allied in groups, from inheriting some
inferiority in common; and therefore as new and improved groups spread
throughout the world, old groups will disappear from the world; and the
succession of forms in both ways will everywhere tend to correspond. There is
one other remark connected with this subject worth making. I have given my
reasons for believing that all our greater fossiliferous formations were
deposited during periods of subsidence; and that blank intervals of vast
duration occurred during the periods when the bed of the sea was either
stationary or rising, and likewise when sediment was not thrown down quickly
enough to embed and preserve organic remains. During these long and blank
intervals I suppose that the inhabitants of each region underwent a
considerable amount of modification and extinction, and that there was much
migration from other parts of the world. As we have reason to believe that
large areas are affected by the same movement, it is probable that strictly
contemporaneous formations have often been accumulated over very wide spaces in
the same quarter of the world; but we are far from having any right to conclude
that this has invariably been the case, and that large areas have invariably
been affected by the same movements. When two formations have been deposited in
two regions during nearly, but not exactly the same period, we should find in
both, from the causes explained in the foregoing paragraphs, the same general
succession in the forms of life; but the species would not exactly correspond;
for there will have been a little more time in the one region than in the other
for modification, extinction, and immigration. I suspect
that cases of this nature have occurred in Europe. Mr. Prestwich, in his
admirable Memoirs on the eocene deposits of England and France, is able to draw
a close general parallelism between the successive stages in the two countries;
but when he compares certain stages in England with those in France, although
he finds in both a curious accordance in the numbers of the species belonging
to the same genera, yet the species themselves differ in a manner very
difficult to account for, considering the proximity of the two areas,—unless,
indeed, it be assumed that an isthmus separated two seas inhabited by distinct,
but contemporaneous, faunas. Lyell has made similar observations on some of the
later tertiary formations. Barrande, also, shows that there is a striking
general parallelism in the successive Silurian deposits of Bohemia and
Scandinavia; nevertheless he finds a surprising amount of difference in the
species. If the several formations in these regions have not been deposited
during the same exact periods,—a formation in one region often corresponding
with a blank interval in the other,—and if in both regions the species have
gone on slowly changing during the accumulation of the several formations and
during the long intervals of time between them; in this case, the several
formations in the two regions could be arranged in the same order, in
accordance with the general succession of the form of life, and the order would
falsely appear to be strictly parallel; nevertheless the species would not all
be the same in the apparently corresponding stages in the two regions. On the
Affinities of extinct Species to each other, and to living forms.—Let us
now look to the mutual affinities of extinct and living species. They all fall
into one grand natural system; and this fact is at once explained on the
principle of descent. The more ancient any form is, the more, as a general
rule, it differs from living forms. But, as Buckland long ago remarked, all
fossils can be classed either in still existing groups, or between them. That
the extinct forms of life help to fill up the wide intervals between existing
genera, families, and orders, cannot be disputed. For if we confine our
attention either to the living or to the extinct alone, the series is far less
perfect than if we combine both into one general system. With respect to the
Vertebrata, whole pages could be filled with striking illustrations from our
great palæontologist, Owen, showing how extinct animals fall in between
existing groups. Cuvier ranked the Ruminants and Pachyderms, as the two most
distinct orders of mammals; but Owen has discovered so many fossil links, that
he has had to alter the whole classification of these two orders; and has
placed certain pachyderms in the same sub-order with ruminants: for example, he
dissolves by fine gradations the apparently wide difference between the pig and
the camel. In regard to the Invertebrata, Barrande, and a higher authority
could not be named, asserts that he is every day taught that palæozoic animals,
though belonging to the same orders, families, or genera with those living at
the present day, were not at this early epoch limited in such distinct groups
as they now are. Some
writers have objected to any extinct species or group of species being
considered as intermediate between living species or groups. If by this term it
is meant that an extinct form is directly intermediate in all its characters
between two living forms, the objection is probably valid. But I apprehend that
in a perfectly natural classification many fossil species would have to stand
between living species, and some extinct genera between living genera, even
between genera belonging to distinct families. The most common case, especially
with respect to very distinct groups, such as fish and reptiles, seems to be,
that supposing them to be distinguished at the present day from each other by a
dozen characters, the ancient members of the same two groups would be
distinguished by a somewhat lesser number of characters, so that the two groups,
though formerly quite distinct, at that period made some small approach to each
other. It is a
common belief that the more ancient a form is, by so much the more it tends to
connect by some of its characters groups now widely separated from each other.
This remark no doubt must be restricted to those groups which have undergone
much change in the course of geological ages; and it would be difficult to
prove the truth of the proposition, for every now and then even a living
animal, as the Lepidosiren, is discovered having affinities directed towards
very distinct groups. Yet if we compare the older Reptiles and Batrachians, the
older Fish, the older Cephalopods, and the eocene Mammals, with the more recent
members of the same classes, we must admit that there is some truth in the
remark. Let us see
how far these several facts and inferences accord with the theory of descent
with modification. As the subject is somewhat complex, I must request the
reader to turn to the diagram in the fourth chapter. We may suppose that the
numbered letters represent genera, and the dotted lines diverging from them the
species in each genus. The diagram is much too simple, too few genera and too
few species being given, but this is unimportant for us. The horizontal lines
may represent successive geological formations, and all the forms beneath the
uppermost line may be considered as extinct. The three existing genera, a14,
q14, p14, will form a small family; b14
and f14 a closely allied family or sub-family; and o14,
e14, m14, a third family. These three
families, together with the many extinct genera on the several lines of descent
diverging from the parent-form A, will form an order; for all will have
inherited something in common from their ancient and common progenitor. On the
principle of the continued tendency to divergence of character, which was
formerly illustrated by this diagram, the more recent any form is, the more it
will generally differ from its ancient progenitor. Hence we can understand the
rule that the most ancient fossils differ most from existing forms. We must
not, however, assume that divergence of character is a necessary contingency;
it depends solely on the descendants from a species being thus enabled to seize
on many and different places in the economy of nature. Therefore it is quite
possible, as we have seen in the case of some Silurian forms, that a species
might go on being slightly modified in relation to its slightly altered
conditions of life, and yet retain throughout a vast period the same general
characteristics. This is represented in the diagram by the letter F14. All the
many forms, extinct and recent, descended from A, make, as before remarked, one
order; and this order, from the continued effects of extinction and divergence
of character, has become divided into several sub-families and families, some
of which are supposed to have perished at different periods, and some to have
endured to the present day. By looking
at the diagram we can see that if many of the extinct forms, supposed to be
embedded in the successive formations, were discovered at several points low
down in the series, the three existing families on the uppermost line would be
rendered less distinct from each other. If, for instance, the genera a1,
a5, a10, f8, m3,
m6, m9 were disinterred, these three
families would be so closely linked together that they probably would have to
be united into one great family, in nearly the same manner as has occurred with
ruminants and pachyderms. Yet he who objected to call the extinct genera, which
thus linked the living genera of three families together, intermediate in
character, would be justified, as they are intermediate, not directly, but only
by a long and circuitous course through many widely different forms. If many
extinct forms were to be discovered above one of the middle horizontal lines or
geological formations—for instance, above No. VI.—but none from beneath this
line, then only the two families on the left hand (namely, a14,
&c., and b14, &c.) would have to be united into one
family; and the two other families (namely, a14 to f14
now including five genera, and o14 to m14)
would yet remain distinct. These two families, however, would be less distinct
from each other than they were before the discovery of the fossils. If, for instance,
we suppose the existing genera of the two families to differ from each other by
a dozen characters, in this case the genera, at the early period marked VI.,
would differ by a lesser number of characters; for at this early stage of
descent they have not diverged in character from the common progenitor of the
order, nearly so much as they subsequently diverged. Thus it comes that ancient
and extinct genera are often in some slight degree intermediate in character
between their modified descendants, or between their collateral relations. In nature
the case will be far more complicated than is represented in the diagram; for
the groups will have been more numerous, they will have endured for extremely
unequal lengths of time, and will have been modified in various degrees. As we
possess only the last volume of the geological record, and that in a very
broken condition, we have no right to expect, except in very rare cases, to
fill up wide intervals in the natural system, and thus unite distinct families or
orders. All that we have a right to expect, is that those groups, which have
within known geological periods undergone much modification, should in the
older formations make some slight approach to each other; so that the older
members should differ less from each other in some of their characters than do
the existing members of the same groups; and this by the concurrent evidence of
our best palæontologists seems frequently to be the case. Thus, on
the theory of descent with modification, the main facts with respect to the
mutual affinities of the extinct forms of life to each other and to living
forms, seem to me explained in a satisfactory manner. And they are wholly
inexplicable on any other view. On this
same theory, it is evident that the fauna of any great period in the earth’s
history will be intermediate in general character between that which preceded
and that which succeeded it. Thus, the species which lived at the sixth great
stage of descent in the diagram are the modified offspring of those which lived
at the fifth stage, and are the parents of those which became still more
modified at the seventh stage; hence they could hardly fail to be nearly
intermediate in character between the forms of life above and below. We must,
however, allow for the entire extinction of some preceding forms, and for the
coming in of quite new forms by immigration, and for a large amount of
modification, during the long and blank intervals between the successive
formations. Subject to these allowances, the fauna of each geological period
undoubtedly is intermediate in character, between the preceding and succeeding
faunas. I need give only one instance, namely, the manner in which the fossils
of the Devonian system, when this system was first discovered, were at once recognised
by palæontologists as intermediate in character between those of the overlying
carboniferous, and underlying Silurian system. But each fauna is not
necessarily exactly intermediate, as unequal intervals of time have elapsed
between consecutive formations. It is no
real objection to the truth of the statement, that the fauna of each period as
a whole is nearly intermediate in character between the preceding and
succeeding faunas, that certain genera offer exceptions to the rule. For
instance, mastodons and elephants, when arranged by Dr. Falconer in two series,
first according to their mutual affinities and then according to their periods
of existence, do not accord in arrangement. The species extreme in character
are not the oldest, or the most recent; nor are those which are intermediate in
character, intermediate in age. But supposing for an instant, in this and other
such cases, that the record of the first appearance and disappearance of the
species was perfect, we have no reason to believe that forms successively
produced necessarily endure for corresponding lengths of time: a very ancient
form might occasionally last much longer than a form elsewhere subsequently
produced, especially in the case of terrestrial productions inhabiting separated
districts. To compare small things with great: if the principal living and
extinct races of the domestic pigeon were arranged as well as they could be in
serial affinity, this arrangement would not closely accord with the order in
time of their production, and still less with the order of their disappearance;
for the parent rock-pigeon now lives; and many varieties between the
rock-pigeon and the carrier have become extinct; and carriers which are extreme
in the important character of length of beak originated earlier than
short-beaked tumblers, which are at the opposite end of the series in this same
respect. Closely
connected with the statement, that the organic remains from an intermediate
formation are in some degree intermediate in character, is the fact, insisted
on by all palæontologists, that fossils from two consecutive formations are far
more closely related to each other, than are the fossils from two remote
formations. Pictet gives as a well-known instance, the general resemblance of
the organic remains from the several stages of the chalk formation, though the
species are distinct in each stage. This fact alone, from its generality, seems
to have shaken Professor Pictet in his firm belief in the immutability of
species. He who is acquainted with the distribution of existing species over
the globe, will not attempt to account for the close resemblance of the
distinct species in closely consecutive formations, by the physical conditions
of the ancient areas having remained nearly the same. Let it be remembered that
the forms of life, at least those inhabiting the sea, have changed almost
simultaneously throughout the world, and therefore under the most different
climates and conditions. Consider the prodigious vicissitudes of climate during
the pleistocene period, which includes the whole glacial period, and note how
little the specific forms of the inhabitants of the sea have been affected. On the
theory of descent, the full meaning of the fact of fossil remains from closely
consecutive formations, though ranked as distinct species, being closely
related, is obvious. As the accumulation of each formation has often been
interrupted, and as long blank intervals have intervened between successive
formations, we ought not to expect to find, as I attempted to show in the last
chapter, in any one or two formations all the intermediate varieties between
the species which appeared at the commencement and close of these periods; but
we ought to find after intervals, very long as measured by years, but only moderately
long as measured geologically, closely allied forms, or, as they have been
called by some authors, representative species; and these we assuredly do find.
We find, in short, such evidence of the slow and scarcely sensible mutation of
specific forms, as we have a just right to expect to find. On the
state of Development of Ancient Forms.—There has been much discussion
whether recent forms are more highly developed than ancient. I will not here
enter on this subject, for naturalists have not as yet defined to each other’s
satisfaction what is meant by high and low forms. But in one particular sense
the more recent forms must, on my theory, be higher than the more ancient; for
each new species is formed by having had some advantage in the struggle for life
over other and preceding forms. If under a nearly similar climate, the eocene
inhabitants of one quarter of the world were put into competition with the
existing inhabitants of the same or some other quarter, the eocene fauna or
flora would certainly be beaten and exterminated; as would a secondary fauna by
an eocene, and a palæozoic fauna by a secondary fauna. I do not doubt that this
process of improvement has affected in a marked and sensible manner the
organisation of the more recent and victorious forms of life, in comparison
with the ancient and beaten forms; but I can see no way of testing this sort of
progress. Crustaceans, for instance, not the highest in their own class, may
have beaten the highest molluscs. From the extraordinary manner in which
European productions have recently spread over New Zealand, and have seized on
places which must have been previously occupied, we may believe, if all the
animals and plants of Great Britain were set free in New Zealand, that in the
course of time a multitude of British forms would become thoroughly naturalized
there, and would exterminate many of the natives. On the other hand, from what
we see now occurring in New Zealand, and from hardly a single inhabitant of the
southern hemisphere having become wild in any part of Europe, we may doubt, if
all the productions of New Zealand were set free in Great Britain, whether any
considerable number would be enabled to seize on places now occupied by our
native plants and animals. Under this point of view, the productions of Great
Britain may be said to be higher than those of New Zealand. Yet the most
skilful naturalist from an examination of the species of the two countries
could not have foreseen this result. Agassiz
insists that ancient animals resemble to a certain extent the embryos of recent
animals of the same classes; or that the geological succession of extinct forms
is in some degree parallel to the embryological development of recent forms. I
must follow Pictet and Huxley in thinking that the truth of this doctrine is
very far from proved. Yet I fully expect to see it hereafter confirmed, at
least in regard to subordinate groups, which have branched off from each other
within comparatively recent times. For this doctrine of Agassiz accords well
with the theory of natural selection. In a future chapter I shall attempt to
show that the adult differs from its embryo, owing to variations supervening at
a not early age, and being inherited at a corresponding age. This process,
whilst it leaves the embryo almost unaltered, continually adds, in the course
of successive generations, more and more difference to the adult. Thus the
embryo comes to be left as a sort of picture, preserved by nature, of the
ancient and less modified condition of each animal. This view may be true, and
yet it may never be capable of full proof. Seeing, for instance, that the
oldest known mammals, reptiles, and fish strictly belong to their own proper
classes, though some of these old forms are in a slight degree less distinct
from each other than are the typical members of the same groups at the present
day, it would be vain to look for animals having the common embryological
character of the Vertebrata, until beds far beneath the lowest Silurian strata
are discovered—a discovery of which the chance is very small. On the
Succession of the same Types within the same areas, during the later tertiary
periods.—Mr. Clift many years ago showed that the fossil mammals
from the Australian caves were closely allied to the living marsupials of that continent.
In South America, a similar relationship is manifest, even to an uneducated
eye, in the gigantic pieces of armour like those of the armadillo, found in
several parts of La Plata; and Professor Owen has shown in the most striking
manner that most of the fossil mammals, buried there in such numbers, are
related to South American types. This relationship is even more clearly seen in
the wonderful collection of fossil bones made by MM. Lund and Clausen in the
caves of Brazil. I was so much impressed with these facts that I strongly
insisted, in 1839 and 1845, on this “law of the succession of types,”—on “this
wonderful relationship in the same continent between the dead and the living.”
Professor Owen has subsequently extended the same generalisation to the mammals
of the Old World. We see the same law in this author’s restorations of the
extinct and gigantic birds of New Zealand. We see it also in the birds of the
caves of Brazil. Mr. Woodward has shown that the same law holds good with
sea-shells, but from the wide distribution of most genera of molluscs, it is
not well displayed by them. Other cases could be added, as the relation between
the extinct and living land-shells of Madeira; and between the extinct and
living brackish-water shells of the Aralo-Caspian Sea. Now what
does this remarkable law of the succession of the same types within the same
areas mean? He would be a bold man, who after comparing the present climate of
Australia and of parts of South America under the same latitude, would attempt
to account, on the one hand, by dissimilar physical conditions for the
dissimilarity of the inhabitants of these two continents, and, on the other
hand, by similarity of conditions, for the uniformity of the same types in each
during the later tertiary periods. Nor can it be pretended that it is an
immutable law that marsupials should have been chiefly or solely produced in
Australia; or that Edentata and other American types should have been solely
produced in South America. For we know that Europe in ancient times was peopled
by numerous marsupials; and I have shown in the publications above alluded to,
that in America the law of distribution of terrestrial mammals was formerly
different from what it now is. North America formerly partook strongly of the
present character of the southern half of the continent; and the southern half
was formerly more closely allied, than it is at present, to the northern half.
In a similar manner we know from Falconer and Cautley’s discoveries, that
northern India was formerly more closely related in its mammals to Africa than
it is at the present time. Analogous facts could be given in relation to the
distribution of marine animals. On the
theory of descent with modification, the great law of the long enduring, but
not immutable, succession of the same types within the same areas, is at once
explained; for the inhabitants of each quarter of the world will obviously tend
to leave in that quarter, during the next succeeding period of time, closely
allied though in some degree modified descendants. If the inhabitants of one
continent formerly differed greatly from those of another continent, so will
their modified descendants still differ in nearly the same manner and degree.
But after very long intervals of time and after great geographical changes,
permitting much inter-migration, the feebler will yield to the more dominant
forms, and there will be nothing immutable in the laws of past and present
distribution. It may be
asked in ridicule, whether I suppose that the megatherium and other allied huge
monsters have left behind them in South America the sloth, armadillo, and
anteater, as their degenerate descendants. This cannot for an instant be
admitted. These huge animals have become wholly extinct, and have left no
progeny. But in the caves of Brazil, there are many extinct species which are
closely allied in size and in other characters to the species still living in
South America; and some of these fossils may be the actual progenitors of
living species. It must not be forgotten that, on my theory, all the species of
the same genus have descended from some one species; so that if six genera,
each having eight species, be found in one geological formation, and in the
next succeeding formation there be six other allied or representative genera
with the same number of species, then we may conclude that only one species of
each of the six older genera has left modified descendants, constituting the
six new genera. The other seven species of the old genera have all died out and
have left no progeny. Or, which would probably be a far commoner case, two or
three species of two or three alone of the six older genera will have been the
parents of the six new genera; the other old species and the other whole genera
having become utterly extinct. In failing orders, with the genera and species
decreasing in numbers, as apparently is the case of the Edentata of South
America, still fewer genera and species will have left modified
blood-descendants. Summary of
the preceding and present Chapters.—I have attempted to show that
the geological record is extremely imperfect; that only a small portion of the
globe has been geologically explored with care; that only certain classes of
organic beings have been largely preserved in a fossil state; that the number
both of specimens and of species, preserved in our museums, is absolutely as
nothing compared with the incalculable number of generations which must have
passed away even during a single formation; that, owing to subsidence being
necessary for the accumulation of fossiliferous deposits thick enough to resist
future degradation, enormous intervals of time have elapsed between the
successive formations; that there has probably been more extinction during the
periods of subsidence, and more variation during the periods of elevation, and
during the latter the record will have been least perfectly kept; that each
single formation has not been continuously deposited; that the duration of each
formation is, perhaps, short compared with the average duration of specific
forms; that migration has played an important part in the first appearance of
new forms in any one area and formation; that widely ranging species are those
which have varied most, and have oftenest given rise to new species; and that varieties
have at first often been local. All these causes taken conjointly, must have
tended to make the geological record extremely imperfect, and will to a large
extent explain why we do not find interminable varieties, connecting together
all the extinct and existing forms of life by the finest graduated steps. He who
rejects these views on the nature of the geological record, will rightly reject
my whole theory. For he may ask in vain where are the numberless transitional
links which must formerly have connected the closely allied or representative
species, found in the several stages of the same great formation. He may
disbelieve in the enormous intervals of time which have elapsed between our
consecutive formations; he may overlook how important a part migration must
have played, when the formations of any one great region alone, as that of
Europe, are considered; he may urge the apparent, but often falsely apparent,
sudden coming in of whole groups of species. He may ask where are the remains
of those infinitely numerous organisms which must have existed long before the
first bed of the Silurian system was deposited: I can answer this latter
question only hypothetically, by saying that as far as we can see, where our
oceans now extend they have for an enormous period extended, and where our
oscillating continents now stand they have stood ever since the Silurian epoch;
but that long before that period, the world may have presented a wholly
different aspect; and that the older continents, formed of formations older
than any known to us, may now all be in a metamorphosed condition, or may lie
buried under the ocean. Passing
from these difficulties, all the other great leading facts in palæontology seem
to me simply to follow on the theory of descent with modification through
natural selection. We can thus understand how it is that new species come in
slowly and successively; how species of different classes do not necessarily
change together, or at the same rate, or in the same degree; yet in the long
run that all undergo modification to some extent. The extinction of old forms
is the almost inevitable consequence of the production of new forms. We can
understand why when a species has once disappeared it never reappears. Groups
of species increase in numbers slowly, and endure for unequal periods of time;
for the process of modification is necessarily slow, and depends on many
complex contingencies. The dominant species of the larger dominant groups tend
to leave many modified descendants, and thus new sub-groups and groups are
formed. As these are formed, the species of the less vigorous groups, from
their inferiority inherited from a common progenitor, tend to become extinct
together, and to leave no modified offspring on the face of the earth. But the
utter extinction of a whole group of species may often be a very slow process,
from the survival of a few descendants, lingering in protected and isolated
situations. When a group has once wholly disappeared, it does not reappear; for
the link of generation has been broken. We can
understand how the spreading of the dominant forms of life, which are those
that oftenest vary, will in the long run tend to people the world with allied,
but modified, descendants; and these will generally succeed in taking the
places of those groups of species which are their inferiors in the struggle for
existence. Hence, after long intervals of time, the productions of the world
will appear to have changed simultaneously. We can
understand how it is that all the forms of life, ancient and recent, make
together one grand system; for all are connected by generation. We can
understand, from the continued tendency to divergence of character, why the
more ancient a form is, the more it generally differs from those now living.
Why ancient and extinct forms often tend to fill up gaps between existing
forms, sometimes blending two groups previously classed as distinct into one;
but more commonly only bringing them a little closer together. The more ancient
a form is, the more often, apparently, it displays characters in some degree
intermediate between groups now distinct; for the more ancient a form is, the
more nearly it will be related to, and consequently resemble, the common
progenitor of groups, since become widely divergent. Extinct forms are seldom
directly intermediate between existing forms; but are intermediate only by a
long and circuitous course through many extinct and very different forms. We
can clearly see why the organic remains of closely consecutive formations are
more closely allied to each other, than are those of remote formations; for the
forms are more closely linked together by generation: we can clearly see why
the remains of an intermediate formation are intermediate in character. The
inhabitants of each successive period in the world’s history have beaten their
predecessors in the race for life, and are, in so far, higher in the scale of
nature; and this may account for that vague yet ill-defined sentiment, felt by
many palæontologists, that organisation on the whole has progressed. If it
should hereafter be proved that ancient animals resemble to a certain extent
the embryos of more recent animals of the same class, the fact will be
intelligible. The succession of the same types of structure within the same
areas during the later geological periods ceases to be mysterious, and is
simply explained by inheritance. If then
the geological record be as imperfect as I believe it to be, and it may at
least be asserted that the record cannot be proved to be much more perfect, the
main objections to the theory of natural selection are greatly diminished or
disappear. On the other hand, all the chief laws of palæontology plainly
proclaim, as it seems to me, that species have been produced by ordinary
generation: old forms having been supplanted by new and improved forms of life,
produced by the laws of variation still acting round us, and preserved by
Natural Selection. |